I'm
continuing to summarize key portions of Tim Keller's book Walking With God
Through Pain and Suffering. I just heard of a friend and his wife who are
now going through crushing loss of a son. So, this book is not just for those
who wish to discuss pain and suffering from an ivory-tower perspective. the
pain is real, and we better get ready for it in our lives. So, here's more from Keller.
Most
attempts to explain why God permits evil seem tepid, shallow, and ultimately
frivolous, according to Alvin Plantinga. As a result, most Christian thinkers
and philosophers have increasingly recommended the believers try not to
formulate reasons but simply mount a defense. This simply seeks to prove that
the argument against God from evil fails. The burden now is on the skeptic. It
is up to the skeptic to make a compelling case that there can't be a God and
evil in the world at the same time. Here's what the skeptic's argument has to
look like: "A truly good and all-powerful God would not want evil to
exist. Evil exists. Therefore, God who is both good and powerful cannot exist."
But the
believer in God can point out that the argument has a hidden premise, namely
that God does not have any good reasons to allow evil to exist. If he has good
reasons, then there is no contradiction between his existence and that of evil.
The skeptic must reply that God cannot possibly have any such reasons. That is
very hard to prove. We know that we often allow suffering in people's lives to
bring about some greater good (doctors, parents,…). There's another assumption
inside the first hidden premise – "If I can't see any reasons God might
have for permitting that evil, then probably he doesn't have any." But
this is obviously false. Our comeback is this: "If God is infinitely
knowledgeable – why couldn't he have morally sufficient reasons for allowing
evil that you can't think of?" We can't know as much as God. If you have a
God infinite and powerful enough for you to be angry at for allowing evil, then
you must at the same time have a God infinite enough to have sufficient reasons
for allowing that evil.
Most people
who see evil object to God's existence not for philosophical reasons but for
visceral ones. But not everyone who experiences radical evil automatically
loses faith in God. The assumption for skeptics is that God, if he exists, has
failed to do the right thing. But this creates a problem for the person who
disbelieves in God. We humans have moral feelings. Now if there is no God,
where do such strong moral feelings and instincts come from? Is it from
evolution? But that can't account for moral obligation. Where do you get a
standard by which our moral feelings and senses are judged as true and others as
false? This happened to C. S. Lewis. He rejected the existence of God because
he hated the evil in the world. But eventually he came to realize that evil and
suffering were a bigger problem for him as an atheist than as a believer in
God. He concluded that the awareness of moral evil in the world was actually an
argument for the existence of God, not against it. His objection to the
existence of God was that he could perceive no moral standard behind the world
– the world was just randomly evil and cruel. But then if there was no God, any
definition of evil was just based on a private feeling of the individual. If
morals are totally subjective, then you can't say Hitler was wrong.
In summary,
the problem of senseless suffering does not go away if you abandon belief in
God. If there is no God, why have a sense of outrage and horror when unjust
suffering occurs? Violence, suffering, and death are completely natural
phenomena. More from his book to follow in the next blog.
No comments:
Post a Comment